<$BlogRSDURL$>

Tuesday, September 15, 2009

Game Theory and Segregation 

I've been watching the "Game Theory" lectures by Ben Polak on the Yale Open Courses site, and he gives an example game that's a bit depressing.

He deals with an abstract game of racial balance. Suppose you have two (large) sets of people of equal size, N green people and N blue people. Suppose that there are also two neighborhoods of equal size that these people can live in.

The nature of game theory is to start with a postulate about what result makes people happy. In his example, he takes an optimistic view of human nature - that all green and blue people would prefer to live in a neighborhood that is split 50%/50% between blue and green. The only racial discrepancy is that a green people prefer to live in green-majority neighborhood rather than blue-majority neighborhood, if the mix is unequal. So if a green person had to choose between a neighborhood that is 40% green and a neighborhood that is 60% green, he will prefer the 60% green. Similarly, blue people prefer to be in the majority in their district rather than in the minority.

This game has three Nash equilibria. A Nash equilibrium is a solution where nobody could improve their situation by changing their decision. Two of the cases are segregated - all the greens are in neighborhood A and all the blues are in neighborhood B, or visa versa. In both these cases, nobody has any desire to change - they cannot improve their happiness by moving, because moving means becoming the minority in the other neighborhood.

The other equilibrium is when each neighborhood is exactly 50% green and 50% blue. Then nobody benefits from switching because they all prefer to be in 50%/50% neighborhoods, and moving would mess that up.

Unfortunately, this last equilibrium is "unstable." If you jostle it a little, say, making the blue/green mix 53%/47% in neighborhood A (and hence 47%/53% in neighborhood B) then a green person in A thinks, "Ideally, I'd love to convince 3% of the greens in B to switch places with 3% of the blues in A, to get back to 50%/50% mix, but, unfortunately, I have no such power over them. However, if I move from A to B, I will be happier than I am now, because I prefer to be in the majority if there is an unequal mix.) Similarly, the blues in neighborhood B have reason to want to move to A. So what happens is a horrible surge towards segregation.

Now, of course, this is only a theoretical game. Still, it's remarkable that, even with an optimistic view where living in the 50%/50% neighborhood is considered ideal by everybody, you get something like a mutual "white flight" just by assuming that people prefer to be in the majority rather than the minority.

Now, most segregation is, of course, not of this kind. But this game can be applied to, say, school choice in public schools. If a school system allows parents to pick schools for their kids, without the system enforcing racial balance in each school, you might well get a self-segregation in the system, even if everything is fair, even if all parents agree they'd prefer perfect racial integration.

On the other hand, consider a converse case. Let's say you have N men and N women. A simple model here might make people prefer to be in the sexual minority in a neighborhood, and even prefer being the only man or woman in a neighborhood. (Okay, that's a bit extreme.) In this case, oddly, the people rush towards purely mixed neighborhoods. In this case, nobody wants to be in the majority, so the rush is towards equality.


Sunday, August 09, 2009

A liberal's definition of libertarianism 

Via Hullabaloo, a query for a definition of libertarianism from a liberal.

Ideologically, libertarianism tries to start from first principals and definitions to define an ideally "free" society. One of the peculiar definitions at the heart of libertarianism is that the things a person owns are essentially considered parts of the self, and threats against property are essentially threats to the self. (An alternative view is to consider the self as part of the person's property - a strict libertarian believes a person should be free to sell herself into slavery.)

Libertarians believe that any government intervention into our lives is the moral equivalent of physical coercion. Strict libertarians will say "taxation is theft."

However, while railing against government intervention, libertarians often take the side of corporations and investors rather than realizing the way that government creates corporations and investment. For example, if I invest my money in a corporation, and that corporation goes broke and bankrupt, I lose my investment, but I am not liable for any of the debts of that corporation. That limited liability is a government protection, not a natural result on libertarian ideals. Yet investment pretty much would not exist if it weren't for the limited liability of investors.

Libertarians often have two arguments to make. One is that it is a morally superior system, since it is based on freedom of person and property. Another is that it is an efficient and effective system. The problem when they make efficiency and effectiveness arguments is that absolutely free markets are not always the most efficient and effective, so it is dangerous for libertarians to move from their moral certitude to arguments about effectiveness and efficiancy. The fact that libertarian ideals lead to unfortunate outcomes that some of us would call "immoral" is not a consideration for libertarians because the outcome springs from their ideal moral system, so, while unfortunate, it is moral. (There is quite a lot of economic research, for example, which shows that racism is a stable economic order, in that those in a racially divided society who stray out of their racial circle will be economically punished.)

Now, what I'm talking about is the ideal of libertarianism. Many people who call themselves libertarians are actually quite fine with state power to restrict personal liberty, they just believe that the state shouldn't get involved in the economy.


Saturday, April 16, 2005

Question for Frist 

Some enterprising reporter ought to ask Senator Frist the following question:
Are you suggesting that all of those judges who were not blocked by the Democrats in the Senate were not people of faith?

Friday, April 01, 2005

Culture of Life? 

It seems to me that some people don't know the difference between "culture" and "cult."


Thursday, March 24, 2005

Blink 

Has there been a more perfect book title for the Bush era than Blink: The Power of Thinking Without Thinking?


Saturday, March 05, 2005

Do Not Call 

Somehow, I'm on every research phone list in the world. I've gotten 10 calls in the last week from people wanting to survey me.

This is pissing me off. Just got one at 8:45PM.


Sunday, February 13, 2005

Well, that Explains Carville and Matlin 

Well, this news explains how Carville and Matlin's marriage survived.


This page is powered by Blogger. Isn't yours?